Aristotelian influence in the formation of medical theory
Mythologic cradle of Greek medical thought
Early Greek medicine contained both natural and supernatural elements. Pharmaka, a
broad term for drugs, referred to applications for magic, for poison, and for curing. The
gods had a large role. The Iliad opened with an epidemic sent by Apollo, and medical
solutions were often a search to discover what offended a particular god. By the time of
Hesiod (~700 B.C.), Asclepian healing ceremonies consisted of a normalized set of
rituals involving abstinence from food and wine, a sacrifice or gift to the god, and a
nocturnal “incubational” period.1
Aristotle stood at the portal between mythical and modern horizons of thought, and was a
prime motivating agent in propelling medicine, not just philosophy, through that portal.
As a natural philosopher, Aristotle’s influence on medicine is two-pronged – first in
terms of immediate causation – his influence on his own students and their intellectual
descendents – and secondly in terms of indirect causation – his influence on medical
debates raging today.
The shift
The Sicilian philosopher (and some speculate physician) Empedocles, whose life
straddled the sixth and fifth centuries B.C., is credited with the notion that everything
existing is composed of four elements – earth, air, fire, and water.2 Alcmaeon of Croton
(~470 B.C.) held to a similar natural scheme, claiming an equality of powers is
responsible for health – moist and dry; cold and hot; bitter and sweet.
An interesting schism over this model developed with which Aristotle was to contend.
Following Empedocles’ lead, Plato ascribed to a four-element theory, having placed
emphasis on universal principles, including the Forms. Alcmaeon, however, believed that
investigation and even dissection, not just philosophy, was necessary to understand the
body (MI, 192).3 Aristotle was to wed Plato’s and Alcmaeon’s two strains of thought.
Aristotle’s influence on Greek medical practice and thought
Aristotle was born 384 B.C. in Stagira, Thrace. His father Nicomachus was a member of
the guild of the Asclepiadae, and his mother Phaestis was a member of the Asclepiad
family. His father was court physician to the King of Macedon, the grandfather of
Alexander the Great. Indeed, it is recorded that Aristotle served for three years as tutor to
Alexander.4 According to Claudius Galen, the Asclepiad families trained their sons from
childhood in anatomy on top of the basic foundation of reading and writing, a course of
study that Aristotle may himself have experienced.5
Nonetheless, Aristotle broke away from his father’s profession, and entered Plato’s
Academy at age eighteen. Like Plato, Aristotle was firmly committed to the belief that
the first principles of medicine should derive from general philosophical principles. The
principles Aristotle adopted included the four-element theory of earth, air, fire, and water.
2
(He also subscribed to a fifth, non-terrestrial element, the “quintessence” or “ether,”
which he believed existed in the heavens.) However, Aristotle’s beliefs additionally
incorporated the criterion of “sensibility” – to him the four-element theory had to meet
standards of theory and observation.
Plato contended that regularities in the patterns of nature are explainable by geometrical
relations between the surfaces of bodies that symbolically represent the four elements.
Aristotle felt that it is impossible for corporeal bodies to be made out of planes. An axiom
of scientific explanation had been violated, he contended: “Perceptible things require
perceptible principles, eternal things eternal principles, corruptible things corruptible
principles” (De Caelo (“On The Heavens”) 306a9-12).6 For Aristotle, the properties of
matter that counted were hot and cold, dry and moist, heavy and light, hard and soft,
viscous and brittle, rough and smooth, coarse and fine (GR, 155). While Aristotle
subscribed to a principled reality, these principles allegedly derived more from the
perception of the world than from the mind. In that sense, his thought was in harmony
with Alcmaeon’s.
Aristotle moved these ideas in two scientific directions. First, he tried to account for
change in the elements. Aristotle realized that matter’s ability to go “crunch” was in need
of explanation. According to him, change between the elements comes about by
transformation of a contrary into its opposite – water turns into air when heat overcomes
cold; air turns into fire when the moist is overpowered by the dry. These simple ideas
bear an uncanny resemblance to modern thermodynamic and convection principles. They
3
may also have had an influence on Western contemporary philosophy. Martin Heidegger,
citing Henri Bergson’s thesis “Quid Aristoteles de loco senserit” (Aristotle’s conception
of place), claimed that Bergson’s view of time was in essence determined by Greek
thought.
The second scientific direction was a deepening of the fourfold theory of the elements
with physiologic observation. The body fluids or humours were composed of varying
proportions of blood (warm and moist); phlegm (cold and moist); yellow bile (warm and
dry); and black bile (cold and dry) (MI, 195).2 Disequilibrium in their balance caused
disease, described in three major phases of progression by Hippocrates (MI, 210).
Aristotle elaborated on the function of the elements with respect to the body. Air is taken
into the body to cool the “innate heat” or pneuma within. Moistness is associated with the
watery composition of the tissues. He describes the semen as “wet and waterlike” (GR,
159). Beyond the substance of the body, the form has “homogeneous parts” (flesh, bone,
and blood) and “heterogeneous parts” (e.g., the face, hand, and foot) (CW, 996-7).
Together, the material and formal levels represented the “three degrees of composition”
of the human body (CW, 1005). This nuanced system carried Aristotle beyond the purely
philosophical domain and into the realm of medical science.
Aristotle’s empirical side
It is little surprise that Aristotle’s approach towards the elemental principles would learn
towards the natural. Diogenes Laërtius cites two separate works by Aristotle on anatomy,
and two treatises by him on medicine. Aristotle in some twenty instances
4
straightforwardly refers to his Anatomai or “Dissections.” This lost work, variously
described by authors as existing in seven to eight volumes, was apparently an illustrated
handbook with zoological commentary (GR, 149).7 Aristotle’s writings indicate that he
dissected many animals (a practice he may have inherited from Alcmaeon) and achieved
considerable skill as a comparative anatomist. He is considered by some to have been the
first individual to have used dissection extensively; by others, to be the first natural
historian.
Aristotle’s empirical investigations moved in the direction of both the human and natural
worlds. Exploration of natural history was done on the isle of Lesbos, where Aristotle
wrote three volumes: History of Animals, Generation of Animals, and Parts of Animals.
In these works he described embryological development in fish and sharks, ruminants’
four-chambered fore-stomachs, and the distinctive sutures of the human skull. Aristotle’s
progressive descriptions of the heart went considerably beyond the Hippocratic writings
(Hippocratic physicians did not dissect human beings), and later provoked a response
from Galen about Aristotle’s method of dissecting as he went about testing the
philosopher’s ideas.
In a very unique way, Aristotle was able to respect both principled philosophy and
observational natural philosophy. Both perspectives on nature led to a personal
exploration of the causes of things, and his classic description in Physics, Book II of the
various causes: material (natural “substance” and “substrata”); formal (the “shape and
5
form of things”); efficient (the “proximate source of change or rest”); and final (the “end
or purpose of a thing”).8
Direct influence on medicine and biology
Aristotle’s tenets were transmitted by way of training students in the Lyceum and his
significant body of writings. Chief among the medical advocates within the Lyceum was
Diocles. Like Aristotle, he ascribed to the four-element theory and believed that the
purpose of respiration was to cool the innate heat (which he contended took place through
the pores of the skin as well as the nose and mouth). He is likely to have played an
influential role in the development of anatomy and physiology within the school.
Aristotle’s successor at the Lyceum, Theophrastus, maintained the biologic tradition by
writing a series of books on botany, the History of Plants and Causes of Plants, which
continued as the most significant contributions to the field even in the Middle Ages (GS,
51-2). Terms coined by Theophrastus, such as carpos (fruit) and pericarpion (seed
vessel), are still being used today.
Claudius Galen, considered to be the most important contributor to medicine in the
several centuries occupying and following the Roman period, was measurably influenced
by Aristotle’s work. While Galen produced many commentaries on the Hippocratic
treatises, his philosophical ideas originate mainly from Aristotle, with some input from
Plato and the Stoics.2 Aristotle’s principle of efficient causes is well exemplified in
Galen’s system of thought. Galen was especially interested in the causation of diseases
and the influence of the environment on people’s health. Like Aristotle, Galen depended
6
on dissection for his discoveries. He agreed with Aristotle’s idea of a functional form
behind natural bodies such as organs, as well as his views of the four humours, having
extended them into psychological types – the phlegmatic, sanguine, choleric, and
melancholic. He valued both reason and observation, but felt logic should be carefully
used to confirm hypotheses.
Aristotle and Galen greatly influenced the orbit of philosopher-physicians during the 10th
and 11th centuries (MI, 313). Persian born physician Avicenna (Arabic: Ibn Sina, 980 –
1037 AD) incorporated Aristotelian logic and Galen’s teachings into medical diagnosis
and treatment. It is said that as a teenager, he read Aristotle’s Metaphysics forty times
before comprehending it through an illuminating commentary by al-Farabi. Like Galen,
Avicenna held to Aristotle’s four humour types, which he associated with signs,
symptoms, and treatments. Avicenna’s The Canon of Medicine began to move humour
theory closer to modern medicine, and served as the standard medical text in Europe
through the 17th century (MI, 310). In The Book of Healing Avicenna recommended two
epistemologic methods: Aristotle’s method of induction, and the method of
experimentation.
Lying at the crossroads between classic and Medieval medical thought and the modern
outlook was a pupil of Avicenna’s, Averroes (Arabic: Ibn Rushd, 1126 – 1198 AD), also
known as “The Commentator” (MI, 313). Living in Cordoba, Spain (then Al-Andalus),
Averroes was commissioned by the Sultan to broadly examine Aristotle’s writings, which
he compiled into three diverse commentaries. Like Aristotle, Averroes believed in and
7
wrote about the importance of dissection, though for him it was a means to strengthen
faith.
Aristotle’s influence on medicine during the Scientific Revolution permeated the work of
English physician William Harvey (1578 – 1657), a self-avowed devotee of Aristotle
since his medical training in Padua.9 It is thought that his hunch or hypothesis on the
circularity of the bloodstream was based on the Aristotelian principle of circular motion
(NL, 4, 15). Harvey in his De Motu Cordis even quotes Aristotle’s depiction of the water
cycle. Despite the use of prior principles concerning circularity and purity of blood (NL,
14, 17; AP, 270), Harvey admonished his readers to weigh all that he was saying in the
light of experience, a conviction grounded in Aristotle.
Aristotle’s active observational approach clearly passed to his followers and their
intellectual progeny. To this day the elucidation of causal mechanisms is of utmost
importance in medical practice and health research.
Indirect influence on medicine and biology
A more indirect influence on medical theory and practice might be traced to Aristotle’s
notion of a final cause. Aristotle explains, “Then there is what is a cause insofar as it is an
end; this is the purpose of a thing; in this sense health, for instance, is the cause of a
man’s going for a walk” (Physica II 194b33-35).8 Closely associated with the notion of
purpose is that of chance, for random chance would seem to indicate that the behavior of
a body or bodies are not governed by some purpose. Aristotle questions the role of
8